Die tradisioneel-konserwatiewe vryheidsbe-skouing van Edmund Burke teenoor dié van moderne konserwatisme
Autor: | Roets, Ernst |
---|---|
Rok vydání: | 2022 |
Předmět: |
conservatism
French revolution rasionalisme Edmund Burke General Arts and Humanities politieke teorie ervaring tradisie individualisme General Social Sciences tradition die goeie political theory liberalism Franse rewolusie individualism experience gemeenskap community freedom the good konserwatisme liberalisme rationalism vryheid |
Zdroj: | Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe, Volume: 62, Issue: 4, Pages: 662-679, Published: DEC 2022 |
ISSN: | 2224-7912 0041-4751 |
DOI: | 10.17159/2224-7912/2022/v62n4a3 |
Popis: | In hierdie artikel word daar aangevoer dat die Britse tradisioneel-konserwatiewe denker Edmund Burke (1729-1797) se vryheidsbeskouing fundamenteel verskil van die vryheids-beskouings wat moderne konserwatisme onderlê. Moderne konserwatisme word aan verskillende strome gekenmerk wat hoofsaaklik deur liberale vertrekpunte onderlê word. Dit sluit in: die libertariese stroom, wat ekonomiese vryheid beklemtoon; die neokonserwatiewe stroom, wat die universalisering van Westerse sosiale orde beklemtoon; en die klassiek-liberale stroom, wat individuele vryheid beklemtoon. Die tradisioneel-konserwatiewe vryheidsbe-skouing van Edmund Burke wyk in drie belangrike opsigte van al hierdie strome af: Eerstens beskou Burke vryheid as iets wat nie van die bevordering van die goeie losgemaak kan word nie; tweedens beskou Burke individue as wesens wat slegs werklik vry kan wees indien hulle hul verantwoordelikhede met betrekking tot hul gemeenskap nakom en sodoende daartoe bydra om hul gemeenskap vry te maak; derdens verwerp Burke politieke teorieë uitdruklik en beroep hom daarteenoor op ervaring as die enigste weg waardeur mense vrygemaak kan word. Gevolglik word vryheid, volgens Burke se ontleding, gekenmerk deur die nakoming van verantwoordelikhede, die bevordering van die goeie - nie net vir die individu nie, maar vir die breër gemeenskap - asook wedersydse respek en verdraagsaamheid tussen gemeen-skappe. Even though Edmund Burke (1729-1797) is regularly described as the "founder of conservatism", it is argued in this article that Burke would not recognise his thinking in what is today regarded as modern conservatism. This is because modern conservatism - and the different strands that constitute it - can more aptly be described as particular strands within the broad framework of liberalism. The reason is that modern conservatism is in many ways built on liberal cornerstones, such as the pursuit of individual freedom, free markets, an appeal to political theory and a quest to universalise its way of thinking. Modern conservatism can be divided into a number of strands. It is argued that the most influential of these strands include: 1) libertarianism, which emphasises economic freedom as the primary determining factor for freedom; 2) individualist conservatism, which emphasises the individualist theories of among others John Locke and Thomas Paine; and 3) neo-conservatism, which emphasises its quest to universalise the Western conception of social order. The traditional conservatism of Edmund Burke - and his conception of freedom in particular - differs from the mainstream strands of modern conservatism in three fundamental ways. These can be summarised as: first, the pursuit of the good as the cornerstone to promote freedom; second, a view of the citizen as someone who finds meaning and fulfilment not by turning inward towards their individual selves, but by participating in the community towards the pursuit of the communal good; and third, by rejecting political theory as an approach to solving societal questions and resorting to experience instead. Burke linked experience to tradition, which he also described as the "wisdom of the ancients". Nonetheless, Burke has been described as a liberal and even as the first post-modern thinker. This can be ascribed to his criticism of the prevailing political forces of his time, his support for the Glorious Revolution of 1688 (according to which monarchical power was limited in favour of parliamentary authority) and his support for American autonomy from British rule. It is argued that Burke does notfit these ideological labels, as Burke's conception of identity and offreedom was fundamentally conservative and hardly reconcilable with the tenets of liberalism and post-modernism. Burkean thought is not characterised by an aversion to change, but rather by a pragmatic approach to political change, which favours gradual change and reform over sudden change and revolution. Therefore, he argued for change in favour of American autonomy from the British Empire. Burke argued that the Americans had developed a different culture than that of the British and that they could therefore not be governed by the British as if they had in fact been British. This, according to Burke's analysis, constituted not freedom, but rather imperialism and oppression, which could be described as the opposite of freedom. Burke clearly distinguished between his own conception of freedom (which places the emphasis on the fulfilment of responsibilities in the context of community) and individual licence (according to which freedom is regarded as a circumstance under which individuals can do whatever they please). In Burke's analysis, freedom can only be achieved by preserving what is good from the past and building upon it towards the good, which is grounded in Christianity. This, he argued, can only be done by valuing experience over theory. For this reason, he rejected the French Revolution's conception of freedom, describing it as unnatural and savage. For Burke, freedom naturally implied that citizens of the community should suppress their immoral appetites. Failing to achieve this or giving in to one's sinful desires was, in Burke's analysis, a state of slavery - not freedom. This is because the pursuit of the good naturally implies that freedom must be connected to the pursuit of virtue rather than licence. Therefore, Burke described freedom as "not solitary, unconnected, individual selfish liberty, " but as liberty "secured by the equality of restraint." It is thus concluded that in Burke's conception of freedom, he did not place the individual at the centre; nor did he define freedom along the lines of unlimited market participation; nor did he attempt to convert other cultures to his way of thinking. |
Databáze: | OpenAIRE |
Externí odkaz: |